Pokaż uproszczony rekord

dc.contributor.authorŻak, Mariola
dc.date.accessioned2025-02-10T09:24:40Z
dc.date.available2025-02-10T09:24:40Z
dc.date.issued2024-11-28
dc.identifier.issn0208-6069
dc.identifier.urihttp://hdl.handle.net/11089/54586
dc.description.abstractIn this paper, the assumptions of Miranda Fricker’s theory of epistemic (in)justice read in the context of the neo-Wittgensteinian philosophical trend, also called therapeutic or resolute approach, will be approximated. The theory in question concerns the issue of unequal participation of the experiences of specific marginalised individuals or their groups in the practices of legal meaning-making. The aim of the paper is to show the role of the said theory in legal theory. In the first step, I will discuss the main assumptions of the theory of epistemic (in)justice and its varieties from the perspective of the lawyer-layperson epistemic dependence. I will also present normative proposals for implementing the ideal of epistemic justice as well as a justification for abandoning such a research approach. In the second step, I will show an alternative to normative approaches in the form of a theoretical innovation consisting in supplementing the assumptions of the epistemic (in)justice theory with a therapeutic-resolute reading of the late Wittgenstein in the hermeneutic perspective. In the third step, I will demonstrate that the full application of the theoretical innovation presented in the previous steps within legal institutions requires taking into account the critical category of legal imagination related to “playing” or the performance of law (the game activity) in the sense of performance studies. The fourth step will be to identify sensitive legal institutions that can be improved by including the categories proposed by the theory in question while taking into account the concept of hermeneutic therapy derived from Type III deliberation. In order to illustrate the application possibilities of the theory of epistemic (in)justice in the area of law, I will use a case study. I will apply the following methods: analytical, thick description, and critical legal studies with elements of feminist research methodology.en
dc.description.abstractW niniejszym artykule przybliżone zostaną założenia teorii (nie)sprawiedliwości epistemicznej Mirandy Fricker odczytywane w kontekście filozoficznego nurtu neowittgensteinowskiego, zwanego też podejściem terapeutycznym lub rozjaśniającym. Teoria będąca przedmiotem analizy dotyczy kwestii nierównomiernego udziału doświadczeń konkretnych marginalizowanych jednostek lub ich grup w praktykach tworzenia znaczenia prawnego. Celem artykułu jest ukazanie roli omawianej teorii w teorii prawa. W pierwszym kroku omówię główne założenia teorii (nie)sprawiedliwości epistemicznej i jej rodzaje w perspektywie problemu zależności epistemicznej prawnik-laik. Przedstawię też normatywne propozycje realizacji ideału sprawiedliwości epistemicznej oraz uzasadnienie rezygnacji z takiego podejścia badawczego. W drugim kroku ukażę alternatywę dla ujęć normatywnych w postaci innowacji teoretycznej polegającej na uzupełnieniu założeń teorii (nie)sprawiedliwości epistemicznej o terapeutyczno-rozjaśniające odczytanie myśli późnego Wittgensteina w perspektywie hermeneutycznej. W trzecim kroku wykażę, że pełna aplikacja przedstawionej w poprzednich etapach innowacji teoretycznej w obrębie instytucji prawnych wymaga uwzględnienia krytycznej kategorii wyobraźni prawniczej odnoszonej do „odgrywania” lub performowania prawa (aktywności growej) w rozumieniu performatyki. Czwarty krok będzie polegał na identyfikacji newralgicznych instytucji prawnych, które mogą być udoskonalane poprzez uwzględnienie kategorii proponowanych przez omawianą teorię z uwzględnieniem koncepcji hermeneutycznej terapii zaczerpniętej z teorii deliberacji typu III. W celu zobrazowania możliwości aplikacyjnych teorii (nie)sprawiedliwości epistemicznej w obszarze prawa posłużę się studium przypadku. Wykorzystam przy tym następujące metody: analityczną, opisu zagęszczonego, krytycznych nauk o prawie z elementami feministycznej metodologii badawczej.pl
dc.language.isoen
dc.publisherWydawnictwo Uniwersytetu Łódzkiegopl
dc.relation.ispartofseriesActa Universitatis Lodziensis. Folia Iuridicaen
dc.rights.urihttps://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0
dc.subjectepistemic (in)justiceen
dc.subjecthermeneutic therapyen
dc.subjectlanguage gamesen
dc.subjectperformance of lawen
dc.subjectlegal imaginationen
dc.subjectdeliberationen
dc.subject(nie)sprawiedliwość epistemicznapl
dc.subjectterapia hermeneutycznapl
dc.subjectgry językowepl
dc.subjectperformowanie prawapl
dc.subjectwyobraźnia prawniczapl
dc.subjectdeliberacjapl
dc.titleThe Theory of Epistemic (In)Justice in the Perspective of the Performance of Law: An Approach Based On The Concept Of Hermeneutic Therapyen
dc.title.alternativeTeoria (nie)sprawiedliwości epistemicznej w perspektywie performowania prawa: podejście oparte na koncepcji terapii hermeneutycznejpl
dc.typeArticle
dc.page.number199-236
dc.contributor.authorAffiliationUniversity of Warsawen
dc.identifier.eissn2450-2782
dc.referencesAnnunziata, Filippo. Giorgio Fabio Colombo. Eds. 2018. Law and Opera. Berlin: Springer.en
dc.referencesBerenstain, Nora. 2016. “Epistemic Exploitation.” Ergo: An Open Access Journal of Philosophy 3(22): 569–590. https://doi.org/10.3998/ergo.12405314.0003.022en
dc.referencesBoncompagni, Anna. 2020. “Prejudice in Testimonial Justification: A Hinge Account.” Episteme 1: 1–18. https://doi.org/10.1017/epi.2021.40en
dc.referencesBoswell, John. 2022. “Narrative Analysis.” In Research Methods in Deliberative Democracy. Edited by Selen A. Ercan, Hans Asenbaum, Nicole Curato, Ricardo F. Mendonça. 333–344. Oxford: Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780192848925.003.0023en
dc.referencesBrożek, Bartosz. 2018. Umysł prawniczy. [The Legal Mind]. Kraków: Copernicus Center Press.en
dc.referencesBublitz, Jan Christoph. 2023. “When is Disbelief Epistemic Injustice? Criminal Procedure, Recovered Memories, and Deformations of Epistemic Subjects.” Criminal Law and Philospohy 2: 1–28. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572–023–09695–3en
dc.referencesBurlando-Salazar, Julian A. 2023. “Preventing the Epistemic Harm of Testimonial Injustice in Lay Witness Credibility Assessments.” Boston University Law Review 103(4): 1245–1285. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572–023–09695–3en
dc.referencesCarter, Terrell. Rachel López. 2024. “If Lived Experience Could Speak: A Method for Repairing Epistemic Violence in Law & The Legal Academy”. Temple University Legal Studies Research Paper No. 2024-26, https://ssrn.com/abstract=4741795 [access: 14.10.2024].en
dc.referencesConstanza-Chock, Sasha. 2020. Design Justice: Community-Led Practices to Build the Worlds We Need. Cambridge, MA–London: The MIT Press.en
dc.referencesCorso, Lucia. 2023. “Epistemic Injustice, Judiciary Reasoning and Stereotypes: From Narrow, to Broad, to Broader.” Milan Law Review 4(2): 100–113. https://doi.org/10.54103/milanlawreview/22186en
dc.referencesCrary, Alice. 2000. “Introduction.” In The New Wittgenstein. Edited by Alice Crary, Rupert Read. 1–18. London–New York: Routledge.en
dc.referencesCrary, Alice. 2002. “What Do Feminists Want in an Epistemology?” In Feminist Interpretations of Ludwig Wittgenstein. Edited by Naomi Scheman, Peg O’Connor. 97–118. Philadelphia: Penn State University Press.en
dc.referencesCrary, Alice. 2018. “The Metodological is Political. What’s the Matter with ‘Analytic Feminism?’” Radical Philosophy 2(2): 47–60.en
dc.referencesDotson, Kristie. 2012. “A Cautionary Tale: On Limiting Epistemic Oppression.” Frontiers: A Journal of Women’s Studies 33(1): 24–47. https://doi.org/10.5250/fronjwomestud.33.1.0024en
dc.referencesDyrda, Adam. 2021. “Epistemologiczne problemy prawoznawstwa.” [Epistemological Problems of Jurisprudence]. In Teoria i filozofia prawa. [Theory and Philosophy of Law]. Edited by Adam Dyrda. 29–32. Warszawa: Wolters Kluwer.en
dc.referencesFerreira, Nuno. 2022. “Utterly Unbelievable: The Discourse of ‘Fake’ SOGI Asylum Claims as a Form of Epistemic Injustice.” International Journal of Refugee Law 34: 303–326. https://doi.org/10.1093/ijrl/eeac041en
dc.referencesFricker, Miranda. 2007. Epistemic Injustice: Power and The Ethics of Knowing. Oxford: Oxford University Press.en
dc.referencesFricker, Miranda. 2013. „Epistemic Justice as a Condition of Political Freedom?” Synthese 190(7): 1317–1332.en
dc.referencesGaakeer, Jeanne. 2024. “Feel, Show, Tell: Affect and Legality in the Trial as Performance.” Law, Culture and the Humanities 20(2): 340–354. https://doi.org/10.1177/174387212311776en
dc.referencesGarcía-Valdecasas, Miguel. 2023. “Are Wittgenstein’s Hinges Rational World-Pictures? The Groundlessness Theory Reconsidered.” Topoi 42: 35–45. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245–022–09830–0en
dc.referencesGlaberson, Stephanie. 2024. “The Epistemic Injustice of Algorithmic Family Policing.” UC Irvine Law Review 14(2): 404–456.en
dc.referencesGonzales, Rose. Jasmine B. 2024. “A Critical Perspective on Testimonial Injustice: Interrogating Witnesses’ Credibility Excess in Criminal Trials. A Comment on Federico Picinali’s 'Evidential Reasoning, Testimonial Injustice and the Fairness of the Criminal Trial’.” Quaestio Facti. Revista Internacional Sobre Razonamiento Probatorio 7: 173–185. https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.33115/udg_bib/qf.i7.23043en
dc.referencesGordon, Randy. 2023. The Performance of Law: Everyday Lawyering at the Intersection of Advocacy and Imagination. Abingdon–New York: Routledge.en
dc.referencesGrygieńć, Janusz. 2021a. “Czy powinniśmy bać się zależności epistemicznej (i jak bardzo)?” [Should We Fear Epistemic Dependence (And How Much)?] Filozofia i Nauka. Studia filozoficzne i interdyscyplinarne 9(1): 11–28.en
dc.referencesGrygieńć, Janusz. 2021b. “Od dyktatury ekspertów do demokracji nieliberalnej. Podejście systemowe do demokracji deliberacyjnej i jego braki.” [From the Dictatorship of Experts to Illiberal Democracy: A Systemic Approach to Deliberative Democracy and Its Shortcomings]. Civitas. Studia z Filozofii Polityki 28(4): 15–40.en
dc.referencesGutiérrez, Natalia Urzola. 2024. “Gender in Climate Litigation in Latin America: Epistemic Justice Through a Feminist Lens.” Journal of Human Rights Practice 16(1): 208–226. https://doi.org/10.1093/jhuman/huad030en
dc.referencesHanan, M. Eve. 2020. “Invisible Prisons.” UC Davis Law Review 54(2): 1185–1244.en
dc.referencesHarding, Brynne. 2020. “R v Theriault: A Case of Epistemic Injustice.” ABlawg.ca 10: 1–12. https://ablawg.ca/wp-content/uploads/2020/10/Blog_BH_Theriault.pdf (accessed: 14.08.2024).en
dc.referencesHendriks, Carolyn M. 2008. “Deliberative Governance in the Context of Power.” Policy and Society 28(3): 173–184.en
dc.referencesHoven, Emilie van den. 2021. “Hermeneutical Injustice and the Computational Turn in Law.” Journal of Cross-disciplinary Research in Computational Law 1(1): 1–13.en
dc.referencesJain, Dipika. Kimberly M. Rhoten. 2020. “Epistemic Injustice and Judicial Discourse on Transgender Rights in India: Uncovering Temporal Pluralism.” Journal of Human Values 26(1): 30–49. https://doi.org/10.1177/0971685819890186en
dc.referencesKjaer, Poul F. 2022. “What is Transformative Law?” European Law Open 1: 760–780. https://doi.org/10.1017/elo.2023.1en
dc.referencesKlimowicz, Katarzyna. 2016. “Utopia w «realistycznej» teorii demokracji przedstawicielskiej i realizm w «utopijnych» teoriach demokracji deliberatywnej i partycypacyjnej.” [Utopia in ‘Realistic’ Theory of Representative Democracy and Realism in ‘Utopian’ Theories of Deliberative and Participatory Democracy]. Hybris. Internetowy Magazyn Filozoficzny 33(2): 33–52.en
dc.referencesKoczanowicz, Leszek. 2020. Lęk i olśnienie. Eseje o kulturze niepokoju. [Anxiety and Lucidity: Reflections on Culture in Times of Unrest]. Warszawa: Instytut Badań Literackich PAN.en
dc.referencesLeiboff, Marett. 2015. “Towards a Jurisprudence of the Embodied Mind – Sarah Lund, Forbrydelsen and the Mindful Body.” Naveiñ Reet: Nordic Journal of Law and Social Research. Special Issue on Law and Art 6: 77–92.en
dc.referencesLevinson, Stanford. Jack M. Balkin. 1991. “Law, Music, and Other Performing Arts.” University of Pennsylvania Law Review 139(6): 1597–1568.en
dc.referencesLevy, Ron. 2018. “The ‘Elite Problem’ in Deliberative Constitutionalism.” In The Cambridge Handbook of Deliberative Constitutionalism. Edited by Ron Levy, Hoi Kong, Graeme Orr, Jeff King. 351–369. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108289474.027en
dc.referencesLobo, Camila. 2022. “Speaking Silences: A Wittgensteinian Inquiry into Hermeneutical Injustice.” Nordic Wittgenstein Review 12: 1–23. https://doi.org/10.15845/nwr.v11.3643en
dc.referencesŁętowska, Ewa. 2005. “Communicare et humanum est – o komunikacyjnej misji prawników i muzyków.” [Communicare et humanum est – on the Communicative Mission of Lawyers and Musicians]. Monitor Prawniczy 1: 3–7.en
dc.referencesMedina, José. 2011. “The Relevance of Credibility Excess in a Proportional View of Epistemic Injustice: Differential Epistemic Authority and the Social Imaginary.” Social Epistemology: A Journal of Knowledge, Culture and Policy 25(2): 15–35. https://doi.org/10.1080/02691728.2010.534568en
dc.referencesMedina, José. 2012. “Hermeneutical Injustice and Polyphonic Contextualism: Social Silences and Shared Hermeneutical Responsibilities.” Social Epistemology: A Journal of Knowledge. Culture and Policy 26(2): 201–220. https://doi.org/10.1080/02691728.2011.652214en
dc.referencesMulcahy, Sean. 2022. “Methodologies of Law and Performance.” Law and Humanities 16(2): 165–182. https://doi.org/10.1080/17521483.2022.2123616en
dc.referencesMuradova, Lala. 2021. “Seeing the Other Side? Perspective-Taking and Reflective Political Judgements in Interpersonal Deliberation.” Political Studies 69(3): 644–664. https://doi.org/10.1177/0032321720916605en
dc.referencesPáez, Andrés. Janaina Matida. 2023. “Editorial of Dossier ‘Epistemic Injustice in Criminal Procedure’.” Revista Brasileira de Direito Processual Penal 9(1): 11–38. https://doi.org/10.22197/rbdpp.v9i1.821en
dc.referencesPeters, Julie Stone. 2022. Law as Performance: Theatricality, Spectatorship, and the Making of Law in Ancient, Medieval, and Early Modern Europe. Oxford: Oxford University Press.en
dc.referencesPicinali, Federico. 2024. “Evidential Reasoning, Testimonial Injustice and the Fairness of the Criminal Trial.” Quaestio facti. Revista Internacional sobre Rezonamiento Probatio 6: 1–35. https://doi.org/10.33115/udg_bib/qf.i6.22888en
dc.referencesPohlhaus Jr., Gaile. 2012. “Relational Knowing and Epistemic Injustice: Toward a Theory of Willful Hermeneutical Ignorance.” Hypatia: A Journal of Feminist Philosophy 27(4): 715–735.en
dc.referencesRalph, Anne E. 2024. “Qualified Immunity, Legal Narrative, and the Denial of Knowledge.” Boston College Law Review 65(4): 1317–1380.en
dc.referencesRodak, Lidia. 2011. “Objective Interpretation as Conforming Interpretation.” Oñati Socio-Legal Series 1(9): 1–11.en
dc.referencesRogacka-Rzewnicka, Maria. 2023. “The Impact of the Concept of Continental (Romano-Germanic) Criminal Procedure on the Phenomenon of ‘Epistemic Injustice’.” Revista Brasileira de Direito Processual Penal 9(3): 1109–1135. https://doi.org/10.22197/rbdpp.v9i3.800en
dc.referencesRogers, Nicole. 2008. “The Play of Law: Comparing Performances in Law and Theatre.” Queensland University of Technology Law and Justice Journal 8(2): 429–443.en
dc.referencesRomańczuk-Grącka, Marta. 2021. “Gaslighting jako forma przemocy psychicznej.” [Gaslighting as a Form of Psychological Violence]. Studia Prawnoustrojowe 52: 411–426. https://doi.org/10.31648/sp.6614en
dc.referencesRosario-Lebrón, Aníbal. 2023. “Law’s Power in Naming & Silencing (reviewing Lisa Washington, Survived & Coerced: Epistemic Injustice in the Family Regulation System, 24 Colum. L. Rev. 1097 (2022)).” Family Law Jotwell: The Journal of Things We Like (Lots) 11. https://family.jotwell.com/laws-power-in-naming-silencing/ (accessed: 6.08.2024).en
dc.referencesSafjan, Marek. Przemysław Mikłaszewicz. 2011. “Granice uprzywilejowania wyrównawczego.” [The Limits of Compensatory Preference]. Przegląd Sejmowy 107(6): 31–45.en
dc.referencesSarat, Austin. Lawrence Douglas. Martha Merrill Umphrey. 2018. Law and Performance. Amherst–Boston: University of Massachusetts Press.en
dc.referencesSchmidt, Eva. 2024. “Epistemic Injustice in Deliberative Mini Publics”. Journal of Deliberative Democracy 20(1): 1-10. https://doi.org/10.16997/jdd.1493en
dc.referencesSkuczyński, Paweł. 2016. “The Attitudes of Lawyers Towards the Constitutional Crisis and the Independence of the Judiciary.” In The Limits of Judicial Independence? Edited by Grzegorz Borkowski. 149–166. Warszawa–Toruń: Krajowa Rada Sądownictwa.en
dc.referencesSkuczyński, Paweł. 2020. “Narrativity of Legal Language in the Law-Making Process.” Archiwum Filozofii Prawa i Filozofii Społecznej 22(1): 1–17. https://doi.org//10.36280/AFPIFS.2020.1.66ENGen
dc.referencesSorial, Sarah. 2022. “Deliberation and the Problems of Exclusion and Uptake: The Virtues of Actively Facilitating Equitable Deliberation and Testimonial Sensibility.” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 25: 215–231. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677–022–10273–0en
dc.referencesSousa, Ronald de. 2009. “Epistemic Feelings.” Mind and Matter 7(2): 139–161.en
dc.referencesSpiegel, Thomas J. 2022. “The Epistemic Injustice of Epistemic Injustice.” Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective 11(9): 75–90.en
dc.referencesStawecki, Tomasz. Jan Winczorek. 2015. “Posłowie.” [Afterword]. In Wykładnia konstytucji. Inspiracje, teorie, argumenty. [Constitutional Interpretation: Inspirations, Theories, Arguments]. Edited by Tomasz Stawecki, Jan Winczorek. 517–528. Warszawa: Wolters Kluwer.en
dc.referencesSullivan, Michael. 2017. “Epistemic Injustice and the Law.” In The Routledge Handbook of Epistemic Injustice. Edited by Ian James Kidd, José Medina, Gaile Pohlhaus Jr. 293–302. Abingdon–New York: Routledge. https://doi.org/10.4324/9781315212043.ch28en
dc.referencesSveinsdóttir, Ásta. 2016. “The Naturalism Question in Feminism.” In The Blackwell Companion to Naturalism. Edited by Kelly James Clark. 49–60. Hoboken: Wiley-Blackwell. https://doi.org/10.1002/9781118657775.ch4en
dc.referencesTobiasz, Marcin. 2016. “Demokracja deliberatywna a władza. Iluzje współdecydowania.” [Deliberative Democracy and Power. Illusions of Co-Decision]. Studia Politologiczne 41: 106–122.en
dc.referencesTobiasz, Marcin. 2021. “Deliberacja jako forma wykluczenia.” [Deliberation as a Form of Exclusion]. Myśl Polityczna 2(8): 31–45.en
dc.referencesUfel, Wojciech. 2023. Granice demokracji. Dylematy deliberacji w perspektywie filozofii gier językowych. [The Limits of Democracy: Dilemmas of Deliberation from the Perspective of the Philosophy of Language Games]. Warszawa: Wydawnictwo Naukowe Scholar.en
dc.referencesUfel, Wojciech. 2025. “Language-Based Critique of Deliberation as a ‘Picture’ in the ‘Album Theory’ of Democracy.” In Wittgenstein and Democratic Politics. Language, Dialogue and Political Forms of Life. Edited by Lotar Rasiński, Anat Bieletzki, Leszek Koczanowicz, Thomas Wallgreen. 274–294. New York–Abingdon: Routledge. https://doi.org/10.4324/9781003485254-17en
dc.referencesWalker, Melanie. 2020. “Why Lawyers and Legal Educators Should Care About (Epistemic) Justice.” International Journal of Clinical Legal Education 27(1): 5–46. https://doi.org/10.19164/ijcle.v27i1.915en
dc.referencesWashington, S. Lisa. 2022. “Survived & Coerced: Epistemic Injustice in the Family Regulation System.” Columbia Law Review 122(4): 1097–1664.en
dc.referencesWittgenstein, Ludwig. 2000a. Dociekania filozoficzne. [Philosophical Investigations]. Translated by Bogusław Wolniewicz. Warszawa: Wydawnictwo Naukowe PWN.en
dc.referencesWittgenstein, Ludwig. 2000b. Tractatus logicus-philosophicus. Translated by Bogusław Wolniewicz. Warszawa: Wydawnictwo Naukowe PWN.en
dc.referencesWittgenstein, Ludwig. 2014. O pewności. [On Certainty]. Translated by Bohdan Chwedeńczuk. Warszawa: Wydawnictwo Aletheia.en
dc.referencesZiemińska, Renata. 2013. Historia sceptycyzmu. W poszukiwaniu spójności. [The History of Skepticism: In Search of Consistency]. Toruń: Wydawnictwo Naukowe Uniwersytetu Mikołaja Kopernika.en
dc.referencesZiółkowski, Michał. 2015. “Zasada równości w prawie.” [Principle of Equality in the Law]. Państwo i Prawo 5: 94–111.en
dc.referencesZirk-Sadowski, Marek. 2021. Wprowadzenie do filozofii prawa. [Introduction to the Legal Philosophy]. Warszawa: Wolters Kluwer.en
dc.referencesConvention of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms of November 4, 1950, Journal of Laws 1993, No. 61, item 284, https://www.echr.coe.int/documents/d/echr/convention_eng.en
dc.referencesConstitution of the Republic of Poland of April 2, 1997, Journal of Laws, 1997, No. 78, item 483 as amended.en
dc.referencesAct of November 17, 1964 – Code of Civil Procedure, Journal of Laws, 2024, item 1568.en
dc.referencesAct of June 26, 1974 – Labour Code, Journal of Laws, 2023, item 1465.en
dc.referencesAct of June 6, 1997 – Code of Criminal Procedure, Journal of Laws, 2024, item 37.en
dc.referencesAct of June 6, 1997 – Criminal Code, Journal of Laws, 2024, item 17.en
dc.referencesAct of August 27, 1997 on Vocational and Social Rehabilitation and Employment of Persons with Disabilities, Journal of Laws, 2024, item 44.en
dc.referencesAct of March 12, 2004 on Social Assistance, Journal of Laws, 2024, item 1283.en
dc.referencesAct of January 6, 2005 on National and Ethnic Minorities and on the Regional Language, Journal of Laws, 2017, item 823.en
dc.referencesAct of July 29, 2005 on Counteracting Domestic Violence, Journal of Laws, 2024, item 424.en
dc.referencesAct of December 2, 2010 on the Implementation of Certain EU Regulations on Equal Treatment, Journal of Laws, 2024, item 1175.en
dc.referencesJudgment of the European Court of Human Rights of January 20, 2022, D.M. and N. v. Italy, 60083/19, https://hudoc.echr.coe.int/#{%22itemid%22:[%22001–215179%22]}en
dc.referencesJudgment of the European Court of Human Rights of December 12, 2023, Przybyszewska and Others v. Poland, 11454/17, https://hudoc.echr.coe.int/?i=001–229391en
dc.referencesJudgment of the European Court of Justice of January 12, 2023, J.K. v. TP S.A., C-356/21, ECLI:EU:C:2023:9.en
dc.referencesJudgment of the Constitutional Court of March 18, 2014, SK 53/12, OTK-A 2014/3, item 32.en
dc.referencesResolution of the Supreme Administrative Court of December 2, 2019, I OPS 1/19, https://orzeczenia.nsa.gov.pl/doc/0CB4DBF3D4en
dc.referencesResolution of the Supreme Court of August 24, 2023, III PZP 1/23, http://www.sn.pl/sites/orzecznictwo/orzeczenia3/iii%20pzp%201–23.pdfen
dc.referencesJudgment of the Regional Court in Lublin of June 20, 2018, VIII Pa 86/18, https://orzeczenia.lublin.so.gov.pl/en
dc.referencesJudgment of the Regional Court in Nowy Sącz of May 14, 2019, III Ca 450/18, https://orzeczenia.nowysacz.so.gov.pl/en
dc.referencesDecision of the Supreme Court of October 20, 2021, II KK 467/21, https://www.sn.pl/sites/orzecznictwo/Orzeczenia3/II%20KK%20467–21.pdfen
dc.referencesDecision of the District Court for Kraków-Krowodrza in Krakow of June 12, 2023, II Kp 589/23/K, unpublished.en
dc.contributor.authorEmailmariolazak@poczta.fm
dc.identifier.doi10.18778/0208-6069.109.10
dc.relation.volume109


Pliki tej pozycji

Thumbnail

Pozycja umieszczona jest w następujących kolekcjach

Pokaż uproszczony rekord

https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0
Poza zaznaczonymi wyjątkami, licencja tej pozycji opisana jest jako https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0