dc.contributor.author | Thomason, Richmond H. | |
dc.date.accessioned | 2021-08-20T06:26:00Z | |
dc.date.available | 2021-08-20T06:26:00Z | |
dc.date.issued | 2021-06-30 | |
dc.identifier.issn | 0138-0680 | |
dc.identifier.uri | http://hdl.handle.net/11089/38702 | |
dc.description.abstract | For as long as there have been theories about common knowledge, they have been exposed to a certain amount of skepticism. Recent more sophisticated arguments question whether agents can acquire common attitudes and whether they are needed in social reasoning. I argue that this skepticism arises from assumptions about practical reasoning that, considered in themselves, are at worst implausible and at best controversial. A proper approach to the acquisition of attitudes and their deployment in decision making leaves room for common attitudes. Postulating them is no worse off than similar idealizations that are usefully made in logic and economics. | en |
dc.language.iso | en | |
dc.publisher | Wydawnictwo Uniwersytetu Łódzkiego | pl |
dc.relation.ispartofseries | Bulletin of the Section of Logic;2 | en |
dc.rights.uri | https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nd/4.0 | |
dc.subject | common knowledge | en |
dc.subject | belief | en |
dc.subject | nonmonotonic logic | en |
dc.subject | practical reasoning | en |
dc.title | Common Knowledge, Common Attitudes and Social Reasoning | en |
dc.type | Other | |
dc.page.number | 229-247 | |
dc.contributor.authorAffiliation | University of Michigan, Philosophy Department, 2251 Angell Hall, 48109-1003 Ann Arbor, Michigan, USA | en |
dc.identifier.eissn | 2449-836X | |
dc.references | [1] R. J. Aumann, Agreeing to Disagree, Annals of Statistics, vol. 4(6) (1976), pp. 1236-1239, DOI: https://doi.org/10.1214/aos/1176343654 | en |
dc.references | [2] S. Bucheli, R. Kuznets, T. Studer, Justifications for Common Knowledge, Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics, vol. 21(1) (2011), pp. 35-60, DOI: https://doi.org/10.3166/jancl.21.35-60 | en |
dc.references | [3] H. H. Clark, C. R. Marshall, Definite Reference and Mutual Knowledge, [in:] A. Joshi, B. Webber, I. Sag (eds.), Elements of Discourse Understanding, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, England (1981), pp. 10-63. | en |
dc.references | [4] H. H. Clark, M. Schober, Understanding by Addressees and Overhearers, Cognitive Psychology, vol. 21(2) (1989), pp. 211-232. | en |
dc.references | [5] M. A. Dummett, Wang's Paradox, [in:] R. Keefe, P. Smith (eds.), Vagueness: A Reader, The MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts (1997), pp. 99-118. | en |
dc.references | [6] J. Geanakoplos, Common Knowledge, [in:] R. Aumann, S. Hart (eds.), Handbook of Game Theory, with Economic Applications, chap. 40, vol. 2, North-Holland, Amsterdam (1994), pp. 1437-1496, DOI: https://doi.org/10.1016/S1574-0005(05)80072-4 | en |
dc.references | [7] P. N. Johnson-Laird, Mutual Ignorance: Comments on Clark and Carlson's Paper, [in:] Mutual Knowledge, Academic Press, London (1982), pp. 40-45. | en |
dc.references | [8] H. Lederman, Common Knowledge, [in:] M. Jankovic, K. Ludwig (eds.), The Routledge Handbook of Collective Intentionality, Routledge, New York (2017), pp. 181-195. | en |
dc.references | [9] H. Lederman, Uncommon Knowledge, Mind, vol. 127(508) (2017), pp. 1069-1105, DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/mind/fzw072 | en |
dc.references | [10] H. Lederman, Two Paradoxes of Common Knowledge: Coordinated Attack and Electronic Mail, Noûs, vol. 52(4) (2018), pp. 921-945, DOI: https://doi.org/10.1111/nous.12186 | en |
dc.references | [11] D. K. Lewis, Convention: A Philosophical Study, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts (1969), DOI: https://doi.org/10.1002/9780470693711 | en |
dc.references | [12] V. Lifschitz, Circumscriptive Theories: A Logic-Based Framework for Knowledge Representation, Journal of Philosophical Logic, vol. 17(3) (1988), pp. 391-441, DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00297512 | en |
dc.references | [13] M. Merritt, G. Taubenfeld, Knowledge in Shared Memory Systems, Distributed Computing Archive, vol. 7 (1991), pp. 99-109, DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/BF02280839 | en |
dc.references | [14] S. Morris, H. S. Shin, Approximate Common Knowledge and Co-ordination: Recent Lessons from Game Theory, Journal of Logic, Language, and Information, vol. 6(2) (1997), pp. 171-190, DOI: https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1008270519000 | en |
dc.references | [15] D. G. Novick, K. Ward, Mutual Beliefs of Multiple Conversants: a Computational Model of Collaboration in Air Traffic Control, [in:] R. Fikes, W. Lehnert (eds.), Proceedings of the Eleventh National Conference on Artificial Intelligence, American Association for Artificial Intelligence, AAAI Press, Menlo Park, California (1993), pp. 196-201. | en |
dc.references | [16] P. Panangaden, K. Taylor, Concurrent Common Knowledge: Defining Agreement for Asynchronous Systems, Distributed Computing, vol. 6(2) (1992), pp. 73-94, DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/BF02252679 | en |
dc.references | [17] C. Paternotte, The Fragility of Common Knowledge, Erkenntnis, vol. 82 (2017), pp. 451-472, DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-016-9828-4 | en |
dc.references | [18] A. Rubinstein, The Electronic Mail Game: Strategic Behavior Under 'Almost Common Knowledge', American Economic Review, vol. 79(3) (1989), pp. 385-391. | en |
dc.references | [19] S. Schiffer, Meaning, Oxford University Press, Oxford (1972). | en |
dc.references | [20] S. Schiffer, Remnants of Meaning, The MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts (1987). | en |
dc.references | [21] H. A. Simon, Rational Choice and the Structure of the Environment, Psychologicial Review, vol. 63(2) (1956), pp. 129-138, DOI: https://doi.org/10.1037/h0042769 | en |
dc.references | [22] D. Sperber, D. Wilson, Mutual Knowledge and Relevance in Theories of Comprehension, [in:] N. Smith (ed.), Mutual Knowledge, Academic Press, London (1982), pp. 61-85. | en |
dc.references | [23] D. Sperber, D. Wilson, Relevance: Communication and Cognition, 1st ed., Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts (1986). | en |
dc.references | [24] D. Sperber, D. Wilson, Relevance: Communication and Cognition, 2nd ed., Blackwell, Oxford (1995). | en |
dc.references | [25] R. Stalnaker, Common Ground, Linguistics and Philosophy, vol. 25(5-6) (2002), pp. 701-721, DOI: https://doi.org/10.1023%2FA%3A1020867916902 | en |
dc.references | [26] R. H. Thomason, The Multiplicity of Belief and Desire, [in:] M. P. Georgeff, A. Lansky (eds.), Reasoning about Actions and Plans, Morgan Kaufmann, Los Altos, California (1987), pp. 341-360. | en |
dc.references | [27] R. H. Thomason, Propagating Epistemic Coordination Through Mutual Defaults I, [in:] R. Parikh (ed.), Theoretical Aspects of Reasoning about Knowledge: Proceedings of the Third Conference (TARK 1990), Morgan Kaufmann, Los Altos, California (1990), pp. 29-39, DOI: https://doi.org/10.5555/1027014.1027022 | en |
dc.references | [28] R. H. Thomason, Modeling the Beliefs of Other Agents, [in:] J. Minker (ed.), Logic-Based Artificial Intelligence, Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht (2000), pp. 375-473, DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4615-1567-8_17 | en |
dc.references | [29] R. H. Thomason, The Beliefs of Other Agents (2001), http://web.eecs.umich.edu/_rthomaso/documents/nmk/otheragents.pdf | en |
dc.references | [30] R. H. Thomason, Belief, Intention, and Practicality: Loosening Up Agents and Their Propositional Attitudes, [in:] F. Lihoreau, M. Rebuschi (eds.), Epistemology, Context, Formalism, Springer Verlag, Berlin (2013), pp. 167-184, DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-02943-6_10 | en |
dc.references | [31] B. C. van Fraassen, Representation of Conditional Probabilities, Journal of Philosophical Logic, vol. 5(3) (1976), pp. 417-430, DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00649400 | en |
dc.contributor.authorEmail | rthomaso@umich.edu | |
dc.identifier.doi | 10.18778/0138-0680.2021.04 | |
dc.relation.volume | 50 | |