dc.contributor.author | Miłkowski, Marcin | |
dc.date.accessioned | 2018-02-22T09:13:31Z | |
dc.date.available | 2018-02-22T09:13:31Z | |
dc.date.issued | 2017 | |
dc.identifier.issn | 1689-4286 | |
dc.identifier.uri | http://hdl.handle.net/11089/24140 | |
dc.description.abstract | In this paper, I show how semantic factors constrain the understanding
of the computational phenomena to be explained so that they help build
better mechanistic models. In particular, understanding what cognitive
systems may refer to is important in building better models of cognitive
processes. For that purpose, a recent study of some phenomena in rats
that are capable of ‘entertaining’ future paths (Pfeiffer and Foster 2013)
is analyzed. The case shows that the mechanistic account of physical
computation may be complemented with semantic considerations, and
in many cases, it actually should. | pl_PL |
dc.description.sponsorship | Publikacja została sfinansowana ze środków Ministerstwa Nauki i Szkolnictwa Wyższego w ramach programu Narodowego Programu Rozwoju Humanistyki przyznanych na podstawie decyzji 0014/NPRH4/H3b/83/2016 - projekt „Przygotowanie i publikacja dwóch anglojęzycznych numerów monograficznych Internetowego Magazynu Filozoficznego HYBRIS” (3bH 15 0014 83). | pl_PL |
dc.language.iso | en | pl_PL |
dc.publisher | Instytut Filozofii Uniwersytetu Łódzkiego | |
dc.relation.ispartofseries | Internetowy Magazyn Filozoficzny Hybris;38 | |
dc.subject | physical computation; semantic account of computation; mechanistic account of computation; mechanistic explanation; causal realization | pl_PL |
dc.title | The False Dichotomy Between Causal Realization and Semantic Computation | pl_PL |
dc.type | Article | pl_PL |
dc.page.number | 1-21 | pl_PL |
dc.contributor.authorAffiliation | Instytut Filozofii i Socjologii Polskiej Akademii Nauk | pl_PL |
dc.references | Alme, Charlotte B., Chenglin Miao, Karel Jezek, Alessandro Treves, Edvard I. Moser, and May-Britt Moser. 2014. “Place Cells in the Hippocampus: Eleven Maps for Eleven Rooms.” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 111 (52):18428–35. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1421056111. | pl_PL |
dc.references | Bechtel, William. 2008. Mental Mechanisms. New York: Routledge (Taylor & Francis Group). | pl_PL |
dc.references | Bechtel, William.2009. “Looking Down, Around, and up: Mechanistic Explanation in Psychology.” Philosophical Psychology 2 | pl_PL |
dc.references | Bechtel, William.2016. “Investigating Neural Representations: The Tale of Place Cells.” Synthese 193 (5):1287–1321. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-014-0480-8. | pl_PL |
dc.references | Berger, Alan. 1980. “Quine on ‘Alternative Logics’ and Verdict Tables.” The Journal of Philosophy 77 (5):259–77. https://doi.org/10.2307/2025755. | pl_PL |
dc.references | Chalmers, David J. 2011. “A Computational Foundation for the Study of Cognition.” Journal of Cognitive Science, no. 12:325–59. | pl_PL |
dc.references | Conklin, John, and Chris Eliasmith. 2005. “A Controlled Attractor Network Model of Path Integration in the Rat.” Journal of Computational Neuroscience 18 (2):183–203. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10827-005-6558-z | pl_PL |
dc.references | Craver, Carl F. 2001. “Role Functions, Mechanisms, and Hierarchy.” Philosophy of Science 68 (1):53–74. | pl_PL |
dc.references | Craver, Carl F.2007. Explaining the Brain. Mechanisms and the Mosaic Unity of Neuroscience. Oxford: Oxford University Press | pl_PL |
dc.references | Craver, Carl F. 2013. “Functions and Mechanisms: A Perspectivalist View.” In Functions: Selection and Mechanisms, edited by Philippe Hunemann, 133–58. Dordrecht: Springer | pl_PL |
dc.references | Cummins, Robert. 1975. “Functional Analysis.” The Journal of Philosophy 72 (20):741–65. | pl_PL |
dc.references | Cummins, Robert. 1996. Representations, Targets, and Attitudes. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. | pl_PL |
dc.references | Deisseroth, Karl, Guoping Feng, Ania K Majewska, Gero Miesenböck, Alice Ting, and Mark J Schnitzer. 2006. “Next-Generation Optical Technologies for Illuminating Genetically Targeted Brain Circuits.” The Journal of Neuroscience : The Official Journal of the Society for Neuroscience 26 (41):10380–86. https://doi.org/10.1523/JNEUROSCI.3863-06.2006. | pl_PL |
dc.references | Dretske, Fred I. 1982. Knowledge and the Flow of Information. 2nded. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. | pl_PL |
dc.references | Flatt, Matthew, Anton van Straaten, Robby Findler, and Jacob Matthews. 2009. Revised6 Report on the Algorithmic Language Scheme. Edited by Michael Sperber. Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press. http://www.r6rs.org | pl_PL |
dc.references | Floridi, Luciano. 2010. Information: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press. | pl_PL |
dc.references | Floridi, Luciano. 2010. Information: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press. | pl_PL |
dc.references | Fresco, Nir. 2010. “Explaining Computation Without Semantics: Keeping It Simple.” Minds and Machines 20 (2):165–81. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11023-010-9199-6 | pl_PL |
dc.references | Fresco, Nir, and Marty J. Wolf. 2013. “The Instructional Information Processing Account of Digital Computation.” Synthese 191 (7):1469–92. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-013-0338-5 | pl_PL |
dc.references | Garson, Justin. 2013. “The Functional Sense of Mechanism.” Philosophy of Science 80 (3):317–33. https://doi.org/10.1086/671173 | pl_PL |
dc.references | Harnad, Stevan. 1990. “The Symbol Grounding Problem.” Physica D 42:335–46 | pl_PL |
dc.references | Krohs, Ulrich. 2004. “Der Begriff Des Designs.” In Eine Theorie Biologischer Theorien. Status Und Gehalt von Funktionsaussagen Und Informationstheoretischen Modellen, 59:70–119. Berlin: Springer | pl_PL |
dc.references | Krohs, Ulrich. 2004. “Der Begriff Des Designs.” In Eine Theorie Biologischer Theorien. Status Und Gehalt von Funktionsaussagen Und Informationstheoretischen Modellen, 59:70–119. Berlin: Springer | pl_PL |
dc.references | Krohs, Ulrich. 2004. “Der Begriff Des Designs.” In Eine Theorie Biologischer Theorien. Status Und Gehalt von Funktionsaussagen Und Informationstheoretischen Modellen, 59:70–119. Berlin: Springer | pl_PL |
dc.references | MacKay, Donald MacCrimmon. 1969. Information, Mechanism and Meaning. Cambridge: M.I.T. Press. | pl_PL |
dc.references | McNaughton, Bruce L, Francesco P Battaglia, Ole Jensen, Edvard I Moser, and May-Britt Moser. 2006. “Path Integration and the Neural Basis of the ‘Cognitive Map’.” Nature Reviews. Neuroscience 7 (8):663–78. https://doi.org/10.1038/nrn1932. | pl_PL |
dc.references | Miłkowski, Marcin. 2013. Explaining the Computational Mind. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. | pl_PL |
dc.references | Miłkowski, Marcin. 2015. “Satisfaction Conditions in Anticipatory Mechanisms.” Biology & Philosophy 30 (5):709–28. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-015-9481-3. | pl_PL |
dc.references | Miłkowski, Marcin. 2016. “Unification Strategies in Cognitive Science.” Studies in Logic, Grammar and Rhetoric 48 (1):13–33. https://doi.org/10.1515/slgr-2016-0053. | pl_PL |
dc.references | Millikan, Ruth Garrett. 2002. “Biofunctions: Two Paradigms.” In Functions: New Essays in the Philosophy of Psychology and Biology, edited by Andrew Ariew, Robert Cummins, and Mark Perlman. New York: Oxford University Press, USA. | pl_PL |
dc.references | Pfeiffer, Brad E, and David J Foster. 2013. “Hippocampal Place-Cell Sequences Depict Future Paths to Remembered Goals.” Nature 497 (7447). Nature Publishing Group:74–79. https://doi.org/10.1038/nature12112 | pl_PL |
dc.references | Piccinini, Gualtiero. 2008. “Computation without Representation.” Philosophical Studies 137 (2):205–41. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-005-5385-4. | pl_PL |
dc.references | Piccinini, Gualtiero. 2015. Physical Computation: A Mechanistic Account. Oxford: Oxford University Press | pl_PL |
dc.references | Plebe, Alessio, and Vivian M. De La Cruz. 2016. Neurosemantics. Vol. 10. Studies in Brain and Mind. Cham: Springer International Publishing. http://link.springer.com/10.1007/978-3-319- 28552-8. | pl_PL |
dc.references | Rescorla, Michael. 2009. “Cognitive Maps and the Language of Thought.” The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 60 (2):377–407. https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/axp012 | pl_PL |
dc.references | Rescorla, Michael.2013. “Against Structuralist Theories of Computational Implementation.” The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 64 (4):681–707. https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/axs017. | pl_PL |
dc.references | Schmidt, Brandy, and A. David Redish. 2013. “Neuroscience: Navigation with a Cognitive Map.” Nature 497 (7447):42–43. https://doi.org/10.1038/nature12095. | pl_PL |
dc.references | Shagrir, Oron. 2001. “Content, Computation and Externalism.” Mind 110 (438):369–400. | pl_PL |
dc.references | Shagrir, Oron.2006. “Why We View the Brain as a Computer.” Synthese 153 (3):393–416. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-006-9099-8. | pl_PL |
dc.references | Shagrir, Oron.2010. “Brains as Analog-Model Computers.” Studies In History and Philosophy of Science Part A 41 (3). Elsevier Ltd:271–79. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2010.07.007 | pl_PL |
dc.references | Tolman, Edward Chace. 1948. “Cognitive Maps in Rats and Men.” Psychological Review 55 (4):189–208. | pl_PL |
dc.references | Vermaas, Pieter E., and Wybo Houkes. 2006. “Technical Functions: A Drawbridge between the Intentional and Structural Natures of Technical Artefacts.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, The dual nature of technical artefacts, 37 (1):5–18. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2005.12.002. | pl_PL |